Skip to main content

Main menu

  • Home
  • Current Issue
  • Content
    • Current Issue
    • Early Access
    • Multimedia
    • Podcast
    • Collections
    • Past Issues
    • Articles by Subject
    • Articles by Type
    • Supplements
    • Plain Language Summaries
    • Calls for Papers
  • Info for
    • Authors
    • Reviewers
    • Job Seekers
    • Media
  • About
    • Annals of Family Medicine
    • Editorial Staff & Boards
    • Sponsoring Organizations
    • Copyrights & Permissions
    • Announcements
  • Engage
    • Engage
    • e-Letters (Comments)
    • Subscribe
    • Podcast
    • E-mail Alerts
    • Journal Club
    • RSS
    • Annals Forum (Archive)
  • Contact
    • Contact Us
  • Careers

User menu

  • My alerts

Search

  • Advanced search
Annals of Family Medicine
  • My alerts
Annals of Family Medicine

Advanced Search

  • Home
  • Current Issue
  • Content
    • Current Issue
    • Early Access
    • Multimedia
    • Podcast
    • Collections
    • Past Issues
    • Articles by Subject
    • Articles by Type
    • Supplements
    • Plain Language Summaries
    • Calls for Papers
  • Info for
    • Authors
    • Reviewers
    • Job Seekers
    • Media
  • About
    • Annals of Family Medicine
    • Editorial Staff & Boards
    • Sponsoring Organizations
    • Copyrights & Permissions
    • Announcements
  • Engage
    • Engage
    • e-Letters (Comments)
    • Subscribe
    • Podcast
    • E-mail Alerts
    • Journal Club
    • RSS
    • Annals Forum (Archive)
  • Contact
    • Contact Us
  • Careers
  • Follow annalsfm on Twitter
  • Visit annalsfm on Facebook
OtherReflections

Beneficent Persuasion: Techniques and Ethical Guidelines to Improve Patients’ Decisions

J. S. Swindell, Amy L. McGuire and Scott D. Halpern
The Annals of Family Medicine May 2010, 8 (3) 260-264; DOI: https://doi.org/10.1370/afm.1118
J. S. Swindell
PhD
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
Amy L. McGuire
JD, PhD
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
Scott D. Halpern
MD, PhD, MBE
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • Article
  • Figures & Data
  • eLetters
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF
Loading

Abstract

Physicians frequently encounter patients who make decisions that contravene their long-term goals. Behavioral economists have shown that irrationalities and self-thwarting tendencies pervade human decision making, and they have identified a number of specific heuristics (rules of thumb) and biases that help explain why patients sometimes make such counterproductive decisions. In this essay, we use clinical examples to describe the many ways in which these heuristics and biases influence patients’ decisions. We argue that physicians should develop their understanding of these potentially counterproductive decisional biases and, in many cases, use this knowledge to rebias their patients in ways that promote patients’ health or other values. Using knowledge of decision-making psychology to persuade patients to engage in healthy behaviors or to make treatment decisions that foster their long-term goals is ethically justified by physicians’ duties to promote their patients’ interests and will often enhance, rather than limit, their patients’ autonomy. We describe techniques that physicians may use to frame health decisions to patients in ways that are more likely to motivate patients to make choices that are less biased and more conducive to their long-term goals. Marketers have been using these methods for decades to get patients to engage in unhealthy behaviors; employers and policy makers are beginning to consider the use of similar approaches to influence healthy choices. It is time for clinicians also to make use of behavioral psychology in their interactions with patients.

  • Decision making
  • professional autonomy
  • informed consent
  • ethics
  • persuasive communication

INTRODUCTION

Physicians frequently encounter patients who make choices that contravene their long-term goals. Smoking, eating poorly, not exercising, failing to get regular mammography and colorectal screenings, and not vaccinating children are among the most obvious of these seemingly bad decisions. More subtly, but also quite commonly, patients make curious treatment decisions. An elderly patient with mild, asymptomatic coronary artery disease might request a percutaneous intervention despite evidence and his clinician’s best judgment that medical therapy would provide a better risk-to-benefit ratio. A patient with surgically resectable lung cancer may opt to forego surgery because she believes it would spread the cancer.1

Behavioral economists have shown that self-thwarting tendencies pervade human decision making, and they have identified a number of specific operating heuristics and biases that help explain why patients sometimes make such counterproductive decisions. In this essay we describe the many ways in which these heuristics and biases influence patients’ decisions and argue that often the most ethically appropriate response will be for physicians to use knowledge of these potentially destructive decisional biases to rebias their patients in ways that promote their health or other long-term goals.

Decision Biases and Heuristics

Traditional models of medical decision making are based on rational choice, which assume that decision makers aim to maximize their utility and that decision makers’ preferences are invariable regardless of how a choice is presented (eg, 60% chance of dying vs a 40% chance of living). Behavioral economists have shown otherwise, however. For example, people tend to over-weigh their utilities for gains and underweigh their utilities for losses, to inaccurately project their utilities in a future time period, to reverse their preferences depending on how their options are framed, and to adopt a passive default position (thereby risking errors of omission) rather than actively make a choice (thereby risking a similar or often smaller error of commission). These biases and heuristics influence all decisions, including medical decisions. Table 1⇓ illustrates a number of these biases and heuristics and provides examples of how they might play out in the clinical setting.3

View this table:
  • View inline
  • View popup
Table 1.

Biases and Heuristics That May Impede Optimal Patient Decisions

Ethical Justification for Beneficent Persuasion and Suggested Techniques

During the past several decades, medicine has shifted away from a model in which physicians were largely charged with making decisions that they believed served their patients’ best interests. Spurred by notorious examples of abuse4 and a growing appreciation for the importance of nonmedical values in decision making, this model came to be viewed as unnecessarily paternalistic. In its place has evolved a model of shared decision making in which clinicians serve to provide medical facts and occasionally recommendations, but patients make the ultimate decisions.5 This model is predicated on the assumption that patients are in the best position to decide their health care goals based on their personal values. The assumption is unassailable—who else could better tap into a patient’s desires? But it also leads to a deceivingly simple conclusion that, given their unique knowledge of their values and goals, patients can consistently make choices that promote those values and goals. This latter premise may often prove incorrect, because the decisional biases and heuristics, introduced in Table 1⇑, cast doubt on the ability of patients to access and act upon their own preferences. These biases and heuristics show that a patient’s thinking, desires, and motivations are often highly dependent on and distorted by context. It may therefore be appropriate for physicians to try to rechannel these contextual influences in ways that assist people in achieving the commonly shared goal of long-term health (or, in cases where long-term health is not the only goal, then in ascertaining and achieving the patient’s other goals). To illustrate these points, we will address a range of clinical situations and provide suggestions for when such rechanneling is appropriate and how to accomplish it.

To promote both the ethical principle of respect for autonomy and the principle of beneficence, physicians must first understand the nature of these heuristics and biases and then learn to recognize when they may be inappropriately influencing their patients’ or their own decisions. In cases where there is one treatment or prevention approach that best helps the patient achieve her long-term goals, physicians should act as beneficent persuaders—using knowledge of decisional psychology to influence the patient to choose that approach (Table 2⇓). For example, if physicians have good reason to believe that patients are falling prey to the availability heuristic (Table 1⇑) and thus making decisions that do not promote their goals, then the physician might counteract this tendency by making other examples more vivid. Imagine a 30 year-old pregnant patient, herself a physician, who after much research and contemplation has elected to forgo amniocentesis because of its attendant risks. This patient changes her mind, however, after seeing one vivid example of an infant with a chromosomal abnormality in the hospital waiting room.16 In this case, the clinician might direct the patient’s attention to the many other children in the waiting room or elsewhere who were born perfectly healthy without amniocentesis. Such an intervention is ethically justified because the best available evidence suggests this woman is not at sufficiently high risk for an abnormal pregnancy to accept the risks of amniocentesis to achieve her goals for health for herself and her fetus. Such explicit efforts to rebias patients may supplement clinicians’ other tools for engaging productively with patients, such as using empathy, respect, negotiation, and other good communication skills.

View this table:
  • View inline
  • View popup
Table 2.

Techniques That May Help Physicians Improve Their Patients’ Decisions

We expect that in cases where there is only one clear medically beneficial choice, for example, taking medication when diagnosed with hypertension and high cholesterol, there will be few objections to clinicians’ using the suggested persuasive rebiasing techniques. More controversial will be cases on the other end of the spectrum, where the best decision for a specific patient is less certain, such as when there is clinical equipoise regarding a treatment’s effectiveness or when the decision to be made requires balancing several different sets of values and goals, such as decisions about termination of a pregnancy. In such cases, the clinician is not ethically justified in attempting to persuade the patient in one direction or another. Instead, clinicians ought to make the patient aware of how some of these decisional biases may be influencing their decision making so as to enhance autonomous choice. For example, a dialysis patient who recently had a leg amputation and was also left by her romantic partner may fall prey to the impact bias (Table 1⇑) and choose to forego dialysis because she thinks that she will never get over this loss.14 Although it may not be clear what choice is in this patient’s best interests (or what her long-term goals are), the clinician should inform her about how the impact bias works (that people tend to overestimate how long and intense their pain will be when something bad happens to them) and make her aware that it may be influencing her decision.

Clear-cut cases may be rare, and in most cases the best clinical decision will be ambiguous. For example, a patient with advanced pulmonary arterial hypertension who is in right-sided heart failure may choose to try recently approved oral therapies despite her clinician’s belief that, given the advanced nature of the disease, a continuous intravenous infusion of epoprostenol gives her the best chance for meaningful survival. Although the clinician may understand the patient’s reluctance to have an indwelling catheter to accommodate the infusion, such preferences may be unduly influenced by the focusing effect and impact bias (Table 1⇑). In this case, the patient may be vulnerable to decision-making biases, but the patient’s best interests are not entirely certain (ie, it is conceivable that some patients may truly prefer avoiding the inconveniences or risks of an indwelling catheter, even if it substantially increases their risk for death from disease progression). In cases entailing such trade-offs, we recommend that the clinician first attempt to understand the patient’s goals and then make the patient aware of how biases (such as focusing effect/side-effect aversion, Table 1⇑) may be negatively affecting her decision making by thwarting those goals. If the patient persists in choosing a treatment approach that the clinician believes is deleterious to her welfare or long-term goals, some clinicians may choose to persuasively rebias the patient by framing the likely consequences starkly (perhaps pictorially). Physicians confronting such ambiguous cases should also consider negotiating alternatives with patients. For example, in caring for this patient with pulmonary arterial hypertension, the clinician might work with the patient to negotiate a trial period of infusion. By exploring and addressing the various concerns that the patient has about the burdens and side effects of an indwelling catheter, this negotiation may also help to de-emphasize counterproductive influences on decisions.

Concerns With Beneficent Persuasion

Some may worry that these persuasive rebiasing techniques could too easily be misused by clinicians to inappropriately bias patients and paternalistically coerce them into making decisions that are inconsistent with their own values and beliefs. We emphasize that clinicians should not use knowledge of decisional psychology to serve their own interests—whether personal, financial, religious, or otherwise. This emphasis inevitably requires some trust that clinicians will prioritize their patients’ interests, but this trust is no different from the trust we must always have in physicians to behave professionally and exercise their fiduciary obligations to their patients. Persuasion using methods garnered from decisional psychology is justified only to the extent that it is in the best interests of the patient. Moreover, a patient’s best interests and goals are determined by the patient, not the physician. The physician is merely ascertaining them and rebiasing the patient toward them.

In many cases, the patient’s goals will primarily focus on longevity and freedom from symptoms, but other goals (eg, maintaining one’s physical appearance or financial security) should also be explored. Of course, physicians also need to be aware of how these same decisional biases and heuristics are influencing their own decisions. Finally, some may also be concerned that any sort of persuasion—even beneficent—is unethical. This view is untenable, because some persuasion, however subtle, is inescapable in the sense that clinicians must always frame things one way or the other. For example, physicians must choose whether to offer lumpectomy or mastectomy first for their patients with breast cancer. Given the potentially differing impacts of options based on the priority of primacy vs recency, even such seemingly trivial decisions may be persuasive. Second, and most important, the persuasion is often more than just beneficent; it is often a way to bring the patient to a well-rounded view of the decision at hand and the issues at stake. Abandoning patients in the decision-making process, leaving them to make their own (potentially bad) decisions, merely pays lip service to the promotion of autonomy.17,18

Using knowledge of decision-making psychology to rebias patients to persuade them to engage in healthy behaviors or make good treatment decisions is ethically justified when the patients’ biases or heuristics are distorting their decisions in harmful and potentially correctable ways. Using methods described in this essay, clinicians may frame health decisions to patients in ways that are more likely to motivate patients to make better choices, ie, less biased and more consistent with their long-term goals. Marketers have used framing and other methods garnered from behavioral psychology and behavioral economics for decades to get people to make unhealthy choices. Employers and policy makers are beginning to consider the use of behavioral psychology to influence healthy choices.19,20 It is time for clinicians to also make use of behavioral psychology in their personal interactions with patients.21

Footnotes

  • Conflicts of interest: none reported

  • Received for publication May 20, 2009.
  • Revision received September 17, 2009.
  • Accepted for publication November 2, 2009.
  • © 2010 Annals of Family Medicine, Inc.

REFERENCES

  1. ↵
    Margolis ML, Christie JD, Silvestri GA, Kaiser L, Santiago S, Hansen-Flaschen J. Racial differences pertaining to a belief about lung cancer surgery: results of a multicenter survey. Ann Intern Med. 2003;139(7):558–563.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  2. Smith DM, Sherriff RL, Damschroder L, Loewenstein G, Ubel PA. Misremembering colostomies? Former patients give lower utility ratings than do current patients. Health Psychol. 2006;25(6):688–695.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  3. ↵
    Klein WM, Stefanek ME. Cancer risk elicitation and communication: lessons from the psychology of risk perception. CA Cancer J Clin. 2007;57(3):147–167.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  4. ↵
    Burten K. Dax’s case. [Documentary film]. Produced by Unicorn Media Inc, for Concern for Dying. USA; 1985.
  5. ↵
    Savulescu J. Rational non-interventional paternalism: why doctors ought to make judgments of what is best for their patients. J Med Ethics. 1995;21(6):327–331.
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  6. Volandes AE, Paasche-Orlow MK, Barry MJ, et al. Video decision support tool for advance care planning in dementia: randomised controlled trial. BMJ. 2009;338:b2159.
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  7. Halpern SD, Ubel PA, Asch DA. Harnessing the power of default options to improve health care. N Engl J Med. 2007;357(13): 1340–1344.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  8. Richard R, van der Pligt J, de Vries N. Anticipated regret and time perspective: changing sexual risk-taking behavior. J Behav Decis Making. 1996;9(3):185–199.
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  9. Cranney M, Walley T. Same information, different decisions: the influence of evidence on the management of hypertension in the elderly. Br J Gen Pract. 1996;46(412):661–663.
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  10. Carling C, Kristoffersen D, Montori V, et al. The effect of alternative summary statistics for communicating risk reduction on decisions about taking statins: a randomized trial. PLoS Med. 2009;6(8): e31000140.
    OpenUrl
  11. Lipkus IM, Klein WMP. Effects of communicating social comparison information on risk perceptions for colorectal cancer. J Health Commun. 2006;11(4):391–407.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  12. Banks SM, Salovey P, Greener S, et al. The effects of message framing on mammography utilization. Health Psychol. 1995;14(2):178–184.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  13. Waters EA, Weinstein ND, Colditz GA, Emmons KM. Reducing aversion to side effects in preventive medical treatment decisions. J Exp Psychol Appl. 2007;13(1):11–21.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  14. ↵
    Halpern J. From Detached Concern to Empathy: Humanizing Medical Practice. 1st ed. London: Oxford University Press; 2001.
  15. Ubel P, Loewenstein G, Jepson C. Disability and sunshine: can hedonic predictions be improved by drawing attention to focusing illusions or emotional adaptation? J Exp Psychol Appl. 2005;11(2):111–123.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  16. ↵
    Ubel P. Free Market Madness: Why Human Nature Is At Odds With Economics—And Why It Matters. 1st ed. Cambidge, MA: Harvard Business Press; 2009.
  17. ↵
    Brock DW, Wartman SA. When competent patients make irrational choices. N Engl J Med. 1990;322(22):1595–1599.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  18. ↵
    Katz J. The Silent World of Doctor and Patient. 1st ed. Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press; 2002.
  19. ↵
    Okie S. The employer as health coach. N Engl J Med. 2007;357 (15):1465–1469.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  20. ↵
    Loewenstein G, Brennan T, Volpp KG. Asymmetric paternalism to improve health behaviors. JAMA. 2007;298(20):2415–2417.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  21. ↵
    Ubel PA. “What should I do, doc?”: Some psychologic benefits of physician recommendations. Arch Intern Med. 2002;162(9):977–980.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
PreviousNext
Back to top

In this issue

The Annals of Family Medicine: 8 (3)
The Annals of Family Medicine: 8 (3)
Vol. 8, Issue 3
1 May 2010
  • Table of Contents
  • Index by author
  • In Brief
Print
Download PDF
Article Alerts
Sign In to Email Alerts with your Email Address
Email Article

Thank you for your interest in spreading the word on Annals of Family Medicine.

NOTE: We only request your email address so that the person you are recommending the page to knows that you wanted them to see it, and that it is not junk mail. We do not capture any email address.

Enter multiple addresses on separate lines or separate them with commas.
Beneficent Persuasion: Techniques and Ethical Guidelines to Improve Patients’ Decisions
(Your Name) has sent you a message from Annals of Family Medicine
(Your Name) thought you would like to see the Annals of Family Medicine web site.
CAPTCHA
This question is for testing whether or not you are a human visitor and to prevent automated spam submissions.
1 + 0 =
Solve this simple math problem and enter the result. E.g. for 1+3, enter 4.
Citation Tools
Beneficent Persuasion: Techniques and Ethical Guidelines to Improve Patients’ Decisions
J. S. Swindell, Amy L. McGuire, Scott D. Halpern
The Annals of Family Medicine May 2010, 8 (3) 260-264; DOI: 10.1370/afm.1118

Citation Manager Formats

  • BibTeX
  • Bookends
  • EasyBib
  • EndNote (tagged)
  • EndNote 8 (xml)
  • Medlars
  • Mendeley
  • Papers
  • RefWorks Tagged
  • Ref Manager
  • RIS
  • Zotero
Get Permissions
Share
Beneficent Persuasion: Techniques and Ethical Guidelines to Improve Patients’ Decisions
J. S. Swindell, Amy L. McGuire, Scott D. Halpern
The Annals of Family Medicine May 2010, 8 (3) 260-264; DOI: 10.1370/afm.1118
Twitter logo Facebook logo Mendeley logo
  • Tweet Widget
  • Facebook Like
  • Google Plus One

Jump to section

  • Article
    • Abstract
    • INTRODUCTION
    • Footnotes
    • REFERENCES
  • Figures & Data
  • eLetters
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF

Related Articles

  • PubMed
  • Google Scholar

Cited By...

  • Persuasive Interventions for Controversial Cancer Screening Recommendations: Testing a Novel Approach to Help Patients Make Evidence-Based Decisions
  • Multidisciplinary Discourse
  • In This Issue: The Nourishment and Support of Family Medicine
  • Google Scholar

More in this TOC Section

  • When the Death of a Colleague Meets Academic Publishing: A Call for Compassion
  • Let’s Dare to Be Vulnerable: Crossing the Self-Disclosure Rubicon
  • Not Like They Used To: The Decline of Procedural Competency in Medical Training
Show more Reflections

Similar Articles

Content

  • Current Issue
  • Past Issues
  • Early Access
  • Plain-Language Summaries
  • Multimedia
  • Podcast
  • Articles by Type
  • Articles by Subject
  • Supplements
  • Calls for Papers

Info for

  • Authors
  • Reviewers
  • Job Seekers
  • Media

Engage

  • E-mail Alerts
  • e-Letters (Comments)
  • RSS
  • Journal Club
  • Submit a Manuscript
  • Subscribe
  • Family Medicine Careers

About

  • About Us
  • Editorial Board & Staff
  • Sponsoring Organizations
  • Copyrights & Permissions
  • Contact Us
  • eLetter/Comments Policy

© 2025 Annals of Family Medicine